- Home
- Stephen Hawking
A Stubbornly Persistent Illusion Page 5
A Stubbornly Persistent Illusion Read online
Page 5
On a superficial consideration equation (2), or (2a), respectively, seems to assert an absurdity. If there is constant transmission of light from S2 to S1, how can any other number of periods per second arrive in S1 than is emitted in S2? But the answer is simple. We cannot regard v2 or respectively v1 simply as frequencies (as the number of periods per second) since we have not yet determined the time in system K. What v2 denotes is the number of periods with reference to the time-unit of the clock U in S2, while v1 denotes the number of periods per second with reference to the identical clock in S1. Nothing compels us to assume that the clocks U in different gravitation potentials must be regarded as going at the same rate. On the contrary, we must certainly define the time in K in such a way that the number of wave crests and troughs between S2 and S1 is independent of the absolute value of time; for the process under observation is by nature a stationary one. If we did not satisfy this condition, we should arrive at a definition of time by the application of which time would merge explicitly into the laws of nature, and this would certainly be unnatural and unpractical. Therefore the two clocks in S1 and S2 do not both give the “time” correctly. If we measure time in S1 with the lock U, then we must measure time in S2 with a clock which goes 1 + Φ/c2 times more slowly than the clock U when compared with U at one and the same place. For when measured by such a clock the frequency of the ray of light which is considered above is at its emission in S2
and is therefore, by (2a), equal to the frequency v1 of the same ray of light on its arrival in S1.
This has a consequence which is of fundamental importance for our theory. For if we measure the velocity of light at different places in the accelerated, gravitation-free system K′, employing clocks U of identical constitution, we obtain the same magnitude at all these places. The same holds good, by our fundamental assumption, for the system K as well. But from what has just been said we must use clocks of unlike constitution, for measuring time at places with differing gravitation potential. For measuring time at a place which, relatively to the origin of the co-ordinates, has the gravitation potential Φ, we must employ a clock which—when removed to the origin of co-ordinates—goes (1 + Φ/c2) times more slowly than the clock used for measuring time at the origin of co-ordinates. If we call the velocity of light at the origin of co-ordinates c0, then the velocity of light c at a place with the gravitation potential Φ will be given by the relation
The principle of the constancy of the velocity of light holds good according to this theory in a different form from that which usually underlies the ordinary theory of relativity.
§ 4. BENDING OF LIGHT-RAYS IN THE GRAVITATIONAL FIELD
From the proposition which has just been proved, that the velocity of light in the gravitational field is a function of the place, we may easily infer, by means of Huyghens’s principle, that light-rays propagated across a gravitational field undergo deflexion. For let E be a wave front of a plane light-wave at the time t, and let P1 and P2 be two points in that plane at unit distance from each other. P1 and P2 lie in the
FIG. 2.
plane of the paper, which is chosen so that the differential coefficient of Φ, taken in the direction of the normal to the plane, vanishes, and therefore also that of c. We obtain the corresponding wave front at time t + dt, or, rather, its line of section with the plane of the paper, by describing circles round the points P1 and P2 with radii c1dt and c2dt respectively, where c1 and c2 denote the velocity of light at the points P1 and P2 respectively, and by drawing the tangent to these circles. The angle through which the light-ray is deflected in the path cdt is therefore
if we calculate the angle positively when the ray is bent toward the side of increasing n′. The angle of deflexion per unit of path of the light-ray is thus
Finally, we obtain for the deflexion which a light-ray experiences toward the side n′ on any path (s) the expression
We might have obtained the same result by directly considering the propagation of a ray of light in the uniformly accelerated system K′, and transferring the result to the system K, and thence to the case of a gravitational field of any form.
By equation (4) a ray of light passing along by a heavenly body suffers a deflexion to the side of the diminishing gravitational potential, that is, on the side directed toward the heavenly body, of the magnitude
FIG. 3.
where k denotes the constant of gravitation, M the mass of the heavenly body, Δ the distance of the ray from the centre of the body. A ray of light going past the Sun would accordingly undergo deflexion to the amount of 4.10–6 = .83 seconds of arc. The angular distance of the star from the centre of the Sun appears to be increased by this amount. As the fixed stars in the parts of the sky near the Sun are visible during total eclipses of the Sun, this consequence of the theory may be compared with experience. With the planet Jupiter the displacement to be expected reaches to about of the amount given. It would be a most desirable thing if astronomers would take up the question here raised. For apart from any theory there is the question whether it is possible with the equipment at present available to detect an influence of gravitational fields on the propagation of light.
*A. Einstein, Jahrbuch für Radioakt. und Elektronik, 4, 1907.
*Of course we cannot replace any arbitrary gravitational field by a state of motion of the system without a gravitational field, any more than, by a transformation of relativity, we can transform all points of a medium in any kind of motion to rest.
*The dimensions of S1 and S2 are regarded as infinitely small in comparison with h.
*See above, pp. 32—34.
*L. F. Jewell (Journ. de Phys., 6, 1897, p. 84) and particularly Ch. Fabry and H. Boisson (Comptes rendus, 148, 1909, pp. 688-690) have actually found such displacements of fine spectral lines toward the red end of the spectrum, of the order of magnitude here calculated, but have ascribed them to an effect of pressure in the absorbing layer.
THE FOUNDATION OF
THE GENERAL THEORY
OF RELATIVITY
BY
A. EINSTEIN
Translated from “Die Grundlage der allgemeinen Relativitätstheorie,” Annalen der Physik, 49, 1916.
A. FUNDAMENTAL CONSIDERATIONS ON THE POSTULATE OF RELATIVITY
§ 1. OBSERVATIONS ON THE SPECIAL THEORY OF RELATIVITY
The special theory of relativity is based on the following postulate, which is also satisfied by the mechanics of Galileo and Newton.
If a system of co-ordinates K is chosen so that, in relation to it, physical laws hold good in their simplest form, the same laws also hold good in relation to any other system of co-ordinates K′ moving in uniform translation relatively to K. This postulate we call the “special principle of relativity.” The word “special” is meant to intimate that the principle is restricted to the case when K′ has a motion of uniform translation relatively to K, but that the equivalence of K′ and K does not extend to the case of non-uniform motion of K′ relatively to K.
Thus the special theory of relativity does not depart from classical mechanics through the postulate of relativity, but through the postulate of the constancy of the velocity of light in vacuo, from which, in combination with the special principle of relativity, there follow, in the well-known way, the relativity of simultaneity, the Lorentzian transformation, and the related laws for the behaviour of moving bodies and clocks.
The modification to which the special theory of relativity has subjected the theory of space and time is indeed far-reaching, but one important point has remained unaffected.
For the laws of geometry, even according to the special theory of relativity, are to be interpreted directly as laws relating to the possible relative positions of solid bodies at rest; and, in a more general way, the laws of kinematics are to be interpreted as laws which describe the relations of measuring bodies and clocks. To two selected material points of a stationary rigid body there always corresponds a distance of quite definite length, which is independent of the loca
lity and orientation of the body, and is also independent of the time. To two selected positions of the hands of a clock at rest relatively to the privileged system of reference there always corresponds an interval of time of a definite length, which is independent of place and time. We shall soon see that the general theory of relativity cannot adhere to this simple physical interpretation of space and time.
§ 2. THE NEED FOR AN EXTENSION OF THE POSTULATE OF RELATIVITY
In classical mechanics, and no less in the special theory of relativity, there is an inherent epistemological defect which was, perhaps for the first time, clearly pointed out by Ernst Mach. We will elucidate it by the following example:—Two fluid bodies of the same size and nature hover freely in space at so great a distance from each other and from all other masses that only those gravitational forces need be taken into account which arise from the interaction of different parts of the same body. Let the distance between the two bodies be invariable, and in neither of the bodies let there be any relative movements of the parts with respect to one another. But let either mass, as judged by an observer at rest relatively to the other mass, rotate with constant angular velocity about the line joining the masses. This is a verifiable relative motion of the two bodies. Now let us imagine that each of the bodies has been surveyed by means of measuring instruments at rest relatively to itself, and let the surface of S1 prove to be a sphere, and that of S2 an ellipsoid of revolution. Thereupon we put the question— What is the reason for this difference in the two bodies? No answer can be admitted as epistemologically satisfactory,* unless the reason given is an observable fact of experience. The law of causality has not the significance of a statement as to the world of experience, except when observable facts ultimately appear as causes and effects.
Newtonian mechanics does not give a satisfactory answer to this question. It pronounces as follows:—The laws of mechanics apply to the space R1, in respect to which the body S1 is at rest, but not to the space R2, in respect to which the body S2 is at rest. But the privileged space R1 of Galileo, thus introduced, is a merely factitious cause, and not a thing that can be observed. It is therefore clear that Newton’s mechanics does not really satisfy the requirement of causality in the case under consideration, but only apparently does so, since it makes the factitious cause R1 responsible for the observable difference in the bodies S1 and S2.
The only satisfactory answer must be that the physical system consisting of S1 and S2 reveals within itself no imaginable cause to which the differing behaviour of S1 and S2 can be referred. The cause must therefore lie outside this system. We have to take it that the general laws of motion, which in particular determine the shapes of S1 and S2, must be such that the mechanical behaviour of S1 and S2 is partly conditioned, in quite essential respects, by distant masses which we have not included in the system under consideration. These distant masses and their motions relative to S1 and S2 must then be regarded as the seat of the causes (which must be susceptible to observation) of the different behaviour of our two bodies S1 and S2. They take over the rôle of the factitious cause R1. Of all imaginable spaces R1, R2, etc., in any kind of motion relatively to one another, there is none which we may look upon as privileged a priori without reviving the above-mentioned epistemological objection. The laws of physics must be of such a nature that they apply to systems of reference in any hind of motion. Along this road we arrive at an extension of the postulate of relativity.
In addition to this weighty argument from the theory of knowledge, there is a well-known physical fact which favours an extension of the theory of relativity. Let K be a Galilean system of reference, i.e. a system relatively to which (at least in the four-dimensional region under consideration) a mass, sufficiently distant from other masses, is moving with uniform motion in a straight line. Let K′ be a second system of reference which is moving relatively to K in uniformly accelerated translation. Then, relatively to K′, a mass sufficiently distant from other masses would have an accelerated motion such that its acceleration and direction of acceleration are independent of the material composition and physical state of the mass.
Does this permit an observer at rest relatively to K′ to infer that he is on a “really” accelerated system of reference? The answer is in the negative; for the above-mentioned relation of freely movable masses to K′ may be interpreted equally well in the following way. The system of reference K′ is unaccelerated, but the space-time territory in question is under the sway of a gravitational field, which generates the accelerated motion of the bodies relatively to K′.
This view is made possible for us by the teaching of experience as to the existence of a field of force, namely, the gravitational field, which possesses the remarkable property of imparting the same acceleration to all bodies.* The mechanical behaviour of bodies relatively to K′ is the same as presents itself to experience in the case of systems which we are wont to regard as “stationary” or as “privileged.” Therefore, from the physical standpoint, the assumption readily suggests itself that the systems K and K′ may both with equal right be looked upon as “stationary,” that is to say, they have an equal title as systems of reference for the physical description of phenomena.
It will be seen from these reflexions that in pursuing the general theory of relativity we shall be led to a theory of gravitation, since we are able to “produce” a gravitational field merely by changing the system of co-ordinates. It will also be obvious that the principle of the constancy of the velocity of light in vacuo must be modified, since we easily recognize that the path of a ray of light with respect to K′ must in general be curvilinear, if with respect to K light is propagated in a straight line with a definite constant velocity.
§ 3. THE SPACE-TIME CONTINUUM. REQUIREMENT OF GENERAL CO-VARIANCE FOR THE EQUATIONS EXPRESSING GENERAL LAWS OF NATURE
In classical mechanics, as well as in the special theory of relativity, the co-ordinates of space and time have a direct physical meaning. To say that a point-event has the X1 coordinate x1 means that the projection of the point-event on the axis of X1, determined by rigid rods and in accordance with the rules of Euclidean geometry, is obtained by measuring off a given rod (the unit of length) x1 times from the origin of coordinates along the axis of X1. To say that a point-event has the X4 co-ordinate x4 = t, means that a standard clock, made to measure time in a definite unit period, and which is stationary relatively to the system of coordinates and practically coincident in space with the point-event,* will have measured off x4 = t periods at the occurrence of the event.
This view of space and time has always been in the minds of physicists, even if, as a rule, they have been unconscious of it. This is clear from the part which these concepts play in physical measurements; it must also have underlain the reader’s reflexions on the preceding paragraph (§ 2) for him to connect any meaning with what he there read. But we shall now show that we must put it aside and replace it by a more general view, in order to be able to carry through the postulate of general relativity, if the special theory of relativity applies to the special case of the absence of a gravitational field.
In a space which is free of gravitational fields we introduce a Galilean system of reference K (x, y, z,t), and also a system of coordinates K′ (x′, y′, z′, t′) in uniform rotation relatively to K. Let the origins of both systems, as well as their axes of Z, permanently coincide. We shall show that for a space-time measurement in the system K′ the above definition of the physical meaning of lengths and times cannot be maintained. For reasons of symmetry it is clear that a circle around the origin in the X, Y plane of K may at the same time be regarded as a circle in the X′, Y′ plane of K′. We suppose that the circumference and diameter of this circle have been measured with a unit measure infinitely small compared with the radius, and that we have the quotient of the two results. If this experiment were performed with a measuring-rod at rest relatively to the Galilean system K, the quotient would be π. With a measuring-rod at rest relatively t
o K′, the quotient would be greater than π. This is readily understood if we envisage the whole process of measuring from the “stationary” system K, and take into consideration that the measuring-rod applied to the periphery undergoes a Lorentzian contraction, while the one applied along the radius does not. Hence Euclidean geometry does not apply to K′. The notion of co-ordinates defined above, which pre-supposes the validity of Euclidean geometry, therefore breaks down in relation to the system K′. So, too, we are unable to introduce a time corresponding to physical requirements in K′, indicated by clocks at rest relatively to K′. To convince ourselves of this impossibility, let us imagine two clocks of identical constitution placed, one at the origin of co-ordinates, and the other at the circumference of the circle, and both envisaged from the “stationary” system K. By a familiar result of the special theory of relativity, the clock at the circumference—judged from K—goes more slowly than the other, because the former is in motion and the latter at rest. An observer at the common origin of co-ordinates, capable of observing the clock at the circumference by means of light, would therefore see it lagging behind the clock beside him. As he will not make up his mind to let the velocity of light along the path in question depend explicitly on the time, he will interpret his observations as showing that the clock at the circumference “really” goes more slowly than the clock at the origin. So he will be obliged to define time in such a way that the rate of a clock depends upon where the clock may be.
We therefore reach this result:—In the general theory of relativity, space and time cannot be defined in such a way that differences of the spatial co-ordinates can be directly measured by the unit measuring-rod, or differences in the time co-ordinate by a standard clock.